WEBVTT 00:01.670 --> 00:03.290 Prof: Okay, good morning. 00:03.290 --> 00:06.630 We're going to make the transition today to talking 00:06.633 --> 00:09.303 about Marxism, the second of the three 00:09.295 --> 00:13.205 Enlightenment traditions that we're going to consider in the 00:13.207 --> 00:15.127 first part of this course. 00:15.130 --> 00:20.290 And I should warn you at the outset that I have something of 00:20.289 --> 00:22.649 a heterodox view of Marx. 00:22.650 --> 00:30.000 I have something of a heterodox view of Marx in that if you went 00:30.003 --> 00:36.193 and read, for instance, there's a book by a man called 00:36.189 --> 00:40.229 Graeme Duncan called Marx and 00:40.232 --> 00:40.982 Mill. 00:40.980 --> 00:45.140 He basically, his story line is that Marx and 00:45.144 --> 00:50.164 Mill operate with fundamentally opposed paradigms, 00:50.160 --> 00:54.930 paradigms meaning foundational assumptions, 00:54.930 --> 00:59.960 so that Marx and Mill make completely incommensurable and 00:59.964 --> 01:04.824 incompatible assumptions about how the world works, 01:04.819 --> 01:10.029 and the political theory that can flow from those assumptions. 01:10.030 --> 01:13.230 And so to some extent they are, he thinks on all the big 01:13.230 --> 01:15.500 questions, speaking past one another. 01:15.500 --> 01:21.260 That they're basically you can't adjudicate, 01:21.260 --> 01:24.110 if you like, the disagreements between them 01:24.105 --> 01:27.215 in part because he thinks they're speaking from 01:27.221 --> 01:29.661 fundamentally opposed paradigms. 01:29.659 --> 01:32.659 I think that view couldn't be more wrongheaded. 01:32.659 --> 01:35.529 Marx and Mill are creatures of the Enlightenment, 01:35.530 --> 01:41.700 both, and therefore we will find in examining Marx, 01:41.700 --> 01:45.190 that just like all of the utilitarians we've already 01:45.191 --> 01:48.871 considered so far, they're both committed to 01:48.873 --> 01:54.443 basing politics on a scientific theory of human association, 01:54.440 --> 02:01.120 and to committing themselves to individual freedom as the basic 02:01.123 --> 02:05.763 and most important principle of politics. 02:05.760 --> 02:16.510 02:16.508 --> 02:20.608 Now, so let's, before we get into the details 02:20.614 --> 02:25.564 of Marx's own argument, let's say a few general things 02:25.557 --> 02:29.567 about Marx as an Enlightenment thinker. 02:29.568 --> 02:34.118 And if we think about the Enlightenment thinkers first of 02:34.116 --> 02:38.656 all as committed to science there's no question that Marx 02:38.664 --> 02:42.974 was committed to a scientific theory of politics. 02:42.970 --> 02:47.150 If you read his attack on Proudhon and the utopian 02:47.149 --> 02:51.839 socialists, for example, it was all about attacking them 02:51.841 --> 02:55.681 for being unscientific in their thinking. 02:55.680 --> 03:00.210 It was all about rejecting sentimentalism or wishful 03:00.205 --> 03:05.705 thinking in trying to understand what was feasible and what was 03:05.705 --> 03:08.275 not feasible in politics. 03:08.280 --> 03:11.480 So Marx has a scientific conception. 03:11.479 --> 03:15.359 Of course it doesn't come within a country mile of the 03:15.355 --> 03:19.665 scientific conceptions we saw both among early Enlightenment 03:19.670 --> 03:23.810 theorists like Bentham, or mature Enlightenment 03:23.805 --> 03:25.705 theorists like Mill. 03:25.710 --> 03:30.830 Rather, Marx is committed to something called the materialist 03:30.830 --> 03:32.880 conception of history. 03:32.878 --> 03:38.318 And the materialist conception of history is the idea that, 03:38.318 --> 03:47.178 to use another one of his rather impenetrable phrases, 03:47.180 --> 03:51.860 he's committed to the idea of dialectical materialism. 03:51.860 --> 03:55.230 You might say, "Well, what is dialectical 03:55.230 --> 03:56.730 materialism?" 03:56.729 --> 04:00.839 This comes from the idea first articulated by a German 04:00.842 --> 04:05.112 philosopher called Hegel that history moves in a kind of 04:05.110 --> 04:07.440 zigzag of fits and starts. 04:07.438 --> 04:13.338 The dialectical idea is that some change gets made, 04:13.342 --> 04:16.652 some innovation gets made. 04:16.649 --> 04:19.709 This, though, breeds a kind of undertow, 04:19.709 --> 04:23.559 a resistance against the change, the first change, 04:23.560 --> 04:29.380 and then you get as a result of the initial change, 04:29.379 --> 04:31.589 the undertow, the kind of pushback, 04:31.589 --> 04:36.399 but which isn't the same as a pushback to where you started 04:36.396 --> 04:38.876 from, you get a new starting point. 04:38.879 --> 04:41.559 So Hegel's famous terms were thesis, 04:41.555 --> 04:44.225 antithesis, and synthesis. 04:44.230 --> 04:46.890 The thesis is a change. 04:46.889 --> 04:52.209 So you get, say, the transition from serfdom to 04:52.209 --> 04:55.099 a market-based society. 04:55.100 --> 04:58.820 Then you get resistance to that market-based society. 04:58.819 --> 05:01.469 You get a new working class comes into being, 05:01.470 --> 05:06.150 let's say, and then that working class becomes the agent 05:06.149 --> 05:10.829 of a new change that will produce its own antithesis and 05:10.827 --> 05:12.357 new synthesis. 05:12.360 --> 05:15.260 So history goes like this, if you like. 05:15.259 --> 05:17.899 It doesn't go in a straight line, but it goes in a 05:17.901 --> 05:18.551 direction. 05:18.550 --> 05:21.270 It goes forward in some sense. 05:21.269 --> 05:26.039 And Hegel's idea had been that history eventually reaches an 05:26.043 --> 05:29.603 ending point, and he thought the ending point 05:29.603 --> 05:32.683 was the Prussian state of his day. 05:32.680 --> 05:36.930 He thought all of history was evolving toward this supreme 05:36.930 --> 05:40.660 highest point of the Prussian state of his day, 05:40.660 --> 05:44.560 and it was guided by the working out of ideas in history. 05:44.560 --> 05:48.780 Marx turns this on his head; on its head I should say, 05:48.778 --> 05:49.918 not on his head. 05:49.920 --> 05:54.240 Marx turns it on its head saying, "Well, 05:54.240 --> 05:59.670 yes history goes in this kind of zigzag direction of thesis, 05:59.670 --> 06:03.160 antithesis, synthesis, and then the synthesis becomes 06:03.160 --> 06:07.110 the new thesis and so on, and yes, it has an endpoint 06:07.113 --> 06:10.343 (which he thinks is a communist utopia), 06:10.339 --> 06:13.539 but it's not driven by ideas. 06:13.540 --> 06:16.110 It's not driven by ideas at all. 06:16.110 --> 06:19.660 Instead it's driven by material interest." 06:19.660 --> 06:23.040 So that's why Marx's view is sometimes called, 06:23.040 --> 06:25.820 as I said, dialectical materialism. 06:25.819 --> 06:32.309 It's driven by material interest, or as Bill Clinton did 06:32.307 --> 06:38.317 put it in the 1992 campaign, "It's the economy, 06:38.324 --> 06:40.334 stupid." 06:40.329 --> 06:42.559 "It's the economy, stupid." 06:42.560 --> 06:48.030 That's the basic idea behind materialism that ideas, 06:48.026 --> 06:53.066 culture, beliefs, all of that stuff is what Marx 06:53.065 --> 06:56.705 referred to as superstructure. 06:56.709 --> 06:59.279 It's not really important. 06:59.279 --> 07:02.639 What is important is the economic base, 07:02.642 --> 07:07.602 so that economic interests drive everything over time. 07:07.600 --> 07:12.130 And if you want to understand how a political system works you 07:12.129 --> 07:15.099 better understand the economic system. 07:15.100 --> 07:18.410 So in this sense it's a very different view than Bentham, 07:18.413 --> 07:21.973 or Mill, or any of these folks because they're really working 07:21.966 --> 07:23.916 in the realm of ideas, right? 07:23.920 --> 07:28.450 They're not Hegelians to be sure, but they think that this 07:28.447 --> 07:33.297 idea of shaping society in terms of their utilitarian calculus 07:33.295 --> 07:36.945 can be used in order to reorganize things. 07:36.949 --> 07:41.709 For Marx that would be a completely absurd agenda. 07:41.709 --> 07:43.739 You have to start with the economy. 07:43.740 --> 07:45.330 It's the economy, stupid. 07:45.329 --> 07:49.769 You have to understand what the power of forces are in the 07:49.769 --> 07:54.519 economy and what the tensions and possibilities are within the 07:54.521 --> 07:58.571 economy before you can understand anything else about 07:58.571 --> 07:59.741 politics. 07:59.740 --> 08:04.900 And in that respect I think one thing you should really get 08:04.903 --> 08:10.693 straight right away is just what Marx thought about capitalism. 08:10.689 --> 08:14.299 How many people here thought Marx was against capitalism? 08:14.300 --> 08:16.990 Marx was against capitalism? 08:16.990 --> 08:18.660 Almost nobody? 08:18.660 --> 08:22.300 Max wasn't against capitalism? 08:22.300 --> 08:25.420 How many think he wasn't against capitalism? 08:25.420 --> 08:26.390 One? 08:26.389 --> 08:29.029 Why do you think he wasn't against capitalism? 08:29.029 --> 08:34.359 Just get to a mic. 08:34.360 --> 08:37.970 Student: He wasn't against capitalism because Marx 08:37.970 --> 08:41.260 thought capitalism was a necessary step in getting to 08:41.263 --> 08:42.153 socialism. 08:42.149 --> 08:44.289 Prof: You're exactly right. 08:44.288 --> 08:47.758 So what Marx thought about capitalism was, 08:47.759 --> 08:51.009 and we're going to understand the reasons for this in detail 08:51.008 --> 08:54.888 in the next couple of lectures, that for a certain phase of 08:54.886 --> 08:56.816 history it was essential. 08:56.820 --> 09:00.620 He thought capitalism was the most innovative, 09:00.620 --> 09:05.090 dynamic, productive mode of production that had ever been 09:05.091 --> 09:08.631 dreamed up, and there was no way you could 09:08.629 --> 09:13.469 even think abut a socialist or a communist society developing 09:13.466 --> 09:16.286 unless you had capitalism first. 09:16.288 --> 09:20.488 And Marx would have had absolutely no sympathy for the 09:20.486 --> 09:24.756 Russian Revolution which was done in a peasant society, 09:24.764 --> 09:28.174 or the Chinese communist system either. 09:28.168 --> 09:32.218 He would have said they were completely premature because in 09:32.224 --> 09:36.074 the end it's going to be capitalism which is necessary to 09:36.072 --> 09:39.922 generate the wherewithal to make socialism possible. 09:39.918 --> 09:43.708 So he wouldn't have had any sympathy with the Leninist or 09:43.708 --> 09:47.158 Stalinist projects, which we'll talk about later. 09:47.159 --> 09:49.389 So he's not against capitalism. 09:49.389 --> 09:53.589 What he thinks about capitalism is that it's sawing off the 09:53.592 --> 09:56.132 branch it's sitting on over time. 09:56.129 --> 10:00.629 That is to say there are basic contradictions within the way 10:00.625 --> 10:04.575 capitalism works, and indeed the very things that 10:04.580 --> 10:08.740 make capitalism the most productive mode of production 10:08.736 --> 10:13.046 ever to have existed in human history at one point, 10:13.048 --> 10:18.818 those very same dynamics ultimately will undermine it. 10:18.820 --> 10:24.030 So in that sense don't think of him as simply against 10:24.034 --> 10:25.344 capitalism. 10:25.340 --> 10:29.570 He, rather, wants to understand the dynamics process that brings 10:29.571 --> 10:32.981 capitalism into being, leads it to maturity, 10:32.976 --> 10:36.426 and eventually leads it to self-destruct. 10:36.428 --> 10:39.008 And that is the story that he's going to tell us. 10:39.009 --> 10:40.889 So he has a scientific theory. 10:40.889 --> 10:45.989 It's a materialist theory, and it's based on this metaphor 10:45.994 --> 10:48.954 of the base and superstructure. 10:48.950 --> 10:54.160 People have come up with other metaphors, skeleton and flesh 10:54.163 --> 10:57.703 and so on, but you can play with them. 10:57.700 --> 11:02.110 But the core idea is that it's the material relations that 11:02.105 --> 11:03.955 shape everything else. 11:03.960 --> 11:09.450 More controversially, though, people might say, 11:09.450 --> 11:12.790 is to say, "Well, Marx is really a believer in 11:12.787 --> 11:15.387 individual rights and freedoms." 11:15.389 --> 11:18.349 Most people say, "What? 11:18.350 --> 11:22.120 Marx, a believer in individual rights and Marx thinking that 11:22.116 --> 11:23.966 freedom is important?" 11:23.970 --> 11:26.190 Most people say, "No, Marx is an 11:26.193 --> 11:27.063 egalitarian. 11:27.058 --> 11:30.298 Marx is all about equality." 11:30.298 --> 11:34.788 And one of the things I'm going to suggest to you in my 11:34.792 --> 11:39.702 exposition of Marx is that that is basically wrongheaded. 11:39.700 --> 11:44.100 You'll see that when we come to talk about his idea of a 11:44.100 --> 11:48.740 communist utopia one of his bumper stickers for that is the 11:48.740 --> 11:52.120 claim that, "The free development of 11:52.115 --> 11:56.375 each is a condition for the free development of all." 11:56.379 --> 11:59.929 "The free development of each is the condition for the 11:59.929 --> 12:01.889 free development of all." 12:01.889 --> 12:04.679 So he's an egalitarian in the sense that, 12:04.678 --> 12:07.458 yes, he wants everybody to have freedom, 12:07.460 --> 12:11.640 and he thinks that that is denied to many people in most 12:11.635 --> 12:13.985 forms of social organization. 12:13.990 --> 12:17.250 But freedom is the most important value, 12:17.250 --> 12:20.680 nonetheless, and he wants to assure it for 12:20.678 --> 12:21.848 everybody. 12:21.850 --> 12:26.300 And related to that, you'll see when we come to talk 12:26.301 --> 12:30.841 about on Wednesday or next Monday the labor theory of 12:30.839 --> 12:34.449 value, that the basic thing that 12:34.450 --> 12:40.810 drives Marx is a theory of alienation from our true selves. 12:40.808 --> 12:45.928 We can't be free unless we're at one with our true selves. 12:45.928 --> 12:50.478 And every system of social organization before communism, 12:50.481 --> 12:53.811 in his view, makes it impossible for us to 12:53.813 --> 12:56.663 be at one with our true selves. 12:56.658 --> 13:01.698 We are alienated from our true natures as productive creatures 13:01.698 --> 13:06.738 by the way in which society is organized, and that's the basic 13:06.738 --> 13:07.728 problem. 13:07.730 --> 13:11.410 So we're denied our capacity for free action, 13:11.407 --> 13:15.077 according to Marx, and he thinks we can never 13:15.083 --> 13:19.433 realize it until we reach this communist utopia. 13:19.428 --> 13:24.698 So the takeaway point is going to be that Marx is an 13:24.697 --> 13:28.827 Enlightenment theorist par excellence. 13:28.830 --> 13:33.910 Passe people like Duncan it's simply not correct to see him as 13:33.913 --> 13:38.253 doing something fundamentally different than the real 13:38.245 --> 13:42.575 Enlightenment thinkers such as Mill and Bentham. 13:42.580 --> 13:46.850 Marx is an Enlightenment thinker, and when you want to 13:46.852 --> 13:51.612 see radical critiques of the Enlightenment you have to go to 13:51.610 --> 13:56.290 people like Burke and other anti-Enlightenment thinkers who 13:56.285 --> 14:00.635 we're going to be getting to after spring break. 14:00.639 --> 14:04.659 A second point related to Marx and individual rights and 14:04.659 --> 14:09.119 freedoms is you're going to see that we're going to go back to 14:09.120 --> 14:13.570 our discussion of Locke, and you're going to discover 14:13.565 --> 14:18.045 that Marx is a true Lockean believer in the workmanship 14:18.048 --> 14:21.158 ideal, not in his theory of science, 14:21.160 --> 14:24.780 but in his theory of rights and entitlements. 14:24.778 --> 14:30.048 Marx is going to embrace a kind of doctrine of self-ownership 14:30.047 --> 14:35.667 and the idea that we own what we make as the basis for his theory 14:35.666 --> 14:39.076 of exploitation, because his theory of 14:39.078 --> 14:43.638 exploitation is going to turn on the claim that people are, 14:43.639 --> 14:47.949 in fact, denied the fruits of their own labor because of the 14:47.951 --> 14:50.291 way that the system is set up. 14:50.288 --> 14:54.468 Well, you could say, "So what? 14:54.470 --> 14:58.430 Why should we care that people are denied the fruits of their 14:58.432 --> 15:02.072 own labor unless they're entitled to the fruits of their 15:02.065 --> 15:05.495 own labor," and indeed that is Marx's view. 15:05.500 --> 15:10.930 So you will see that--I was once accused of belittling Marx 15:10.934 --> 15:14.594 by calling him a minor post-Lockean, 15:14.590 --> 15:19.040 but with respect to the labor theory of value you will see 15:19.041 --> 15:23.881 that the main conceptual ideas that go into it are straight out 15:23.881 --> 15:27.791 of Locke's Second Treatise and it's straight 15:27.785 --> 15:30.515 out of the workmanship ideal. 15:30.519 --> 15:34.259 What Marx is going to try and do, when we get to the labor 15:34.263 --> 15:37.153 theory of value, is give a secular version of 15:37.152 --> 15:38.862 the workmanship ideal. 15:38.860 --> 15:42.990 And indeed, developing a viable secular version of the 15:42.988 --> 15:47.738 workmanship ideal is a project with at least as long a history 15:47.740 --> 15:50.700 as the history of utilitarianism, 15:50.700 --> 15:55.030 and at least as fraught with difficulties as the history of 15:55.029 --> 15:56.299 utilitarianism. 15:56.298 --> 15:58.778 And we will see when we get to Rawls, 15:58.779 --> 16:02.819 an even more radical attempt than Marx to develop secular 16:02.818 --> 16:07.578 version of the labor theory of value and the workmanship model, 16:07.580 --> 16:10.620 and the difficulties it runs into. 16:10.620 --> 16:14.700 So Marx, we will see, is the first in a long line of 16:14.697 --> 16:19.007 people who tried to secularize the workmanship ideal by 16:19.014 --> 16:23.574 creating this labor theory of value that's going to have a 16:23.572 --> 16:28.212 rather checkered future as we explore it into the twentieth 16:28.210 --> 16:29.490 century. 16:29.490 --> 16:31.020 So that's where we're heading. 16:31.019 --> 16:35.519 We're going to explore Marx as an Enlightenment thinker by 16:35.518 --> 16:40.768 means of three lectures, and the first one is going to 16:40.769 --> 16:47.759 deal with Marx and the challenge of classical political economy. 16:47.759 --> 16:49.279 Now, why do I say that? 16:49.279 --> 16:53.049 Because really there are two Marxes. 16:53.048 --> 16:57.548 If you were taking a course in the history of ideas that had 16:57.546 --> 17:00.286 more than three lectures on Marx, 17:00.288 --> 17:06.278 what you would discover is a lot of attention to his German 17:06.282 --> 17:07.112 roots. 17:07.108 --> 17:10.338 I've already mentioned that he was a disciple and critic of 17:10.337 --> 17:12.507 Hegel, the German idealist 17:12.513 --> 17:17.803 philosopher, but much of his writing until the mid-nineteenth 17:17.801 --> 17:22.381 century was inspired by his critique of Hegel's other 17:22.384 --> 17:26.284 followers and disciples, and we're pretty much not going 17:26.276 --> 17:27.036 to deal with that. 17:27.038 --> 17:29.738 We're not going to deal with the German Marx. 17:29.740 --> 17:32.710 We're not, by in large, going to deal with the young 17:32.711 --> 17:33.121 Marx. 17:33.118 --> 17:37.818 Rather, what happened to him was Marx thought--you may or may 17:37.823 --> 17:41.043 not know this, but in the 1830s there were 17:41.038 --> 17:43.388 revolutions across Europe. 17:43.390 --> 17:48.440 Kings and queens were kicked out of office and democracy came 17:48.442 --> 17:49.372 to power. 17:49.368 --> 17:52.728 And Marx and many of those around him thought this is the 17:52.730 --> 17:54.950 beginning of the end of capitalism. 17:54.950 --> 17:58.590 By 1832 or 1833, all of those democratic 17:58.590 --> 18:03.260 revolutions had failed, and the monarchies had been 18:03.259 --> 18:05.779 restored across Europe. 18:05.778 --> 18:11.328 But then in 1848 there was another whole series of 18:11.333 --> 18:16.513 revolutions across Europe, and once again Marx thought 18:16.509 --> 18:19.379 maybe this is the beginning of the end, 18:19.380 --> 18:22.630 and had great faith and optimism that that was going to 18:22.626 --> 18:23.466 be the case. 18:23.470 --> 18:27.640 But by 1851 those revolutions had all, again, 18:27.642 --> 18:31.912 failed and the monarchs were back in power. 18:31.910 --> 18:36.540 And Marx, after that, became steadily more dejected 18:36.539 --> 18:42.189 and steadily more skeptical over his remaining years that, 18:42.190 --> 18:45.750 in fact, he was going to see a communist revolution in his 18:45.751 --> 18:46.441 lifetime. 18:46.440 --> 18:51.880 And rather, he invested in the project of trying to understand 18:51.878 --> 18:56.868 capitalism in a much more systematic way than he had done 18:56.873 --> 18:58.393 in his youth. 18:58.390 --> 19:00.900 He was kicked out of Germany. 19:00.900 --> 19:04.690 He couldn't go to France and he wound up in London, 19:04.690 --> 19:08.560 and he lived the last decades of his life in London, 19:08.556 --> 19:11.736 and in fact died and was buried there. 19:11.740 --> 19:16.840 If you're ever in London you can go up to Highgate Cemetery 19:16.837 --> 19:18.857 on the Northern Line. 19:18.858 --> 19:20.378 It's a very interesting cemetery. 19:20.380 --> 19:21.820 There are all kinds of interesting people there. 19:21.819 --> 19:23.539 George Eliot is there. 19:23.538 --> 19:27.748 Anyway, there is Karl Marx in Highgate Cemetery. 19:27.750 --> 19:30.610 It's all overgrown and very interesting. 19:30.608 --> 19:34.378 Anyway, he spent his last decades working in the basement 19:34.384 --> 19:38.114 of the British Museum, and that's where he composed 19:38.108 --> 19:41.508 his magnum opus, his three-volume work Das 19:41.509 --> 19:42.479 Kapital. 19:42.480 --> 19:46.470 It was actually envisaged as a twelve-volume work, 19:46.471 --> 19:51.111 and the only volume that was published in his lifetime was 19:51.114 --> 19:53.074 actually volume one. 19:53.068 --> 19:57.408 The second and third volumes were put together by his friend 19:57.411 --> 20:00.061 and collaborator Friedrich Engels. 20:00.058 --> 20:05.718 And unfortunately for us the volumes about politics were 20:05.721 --> 20:07.371 never written. 20:07.368 --> 20:10.128 So you have to, to some extent, 20:10.125 --> 20:15.445 put together his mature views about politics from scraps he 20:15.451 --> 20:20.741 wrote here and there, and some of the short pieces 20:20.743 --> 20:26.143 about politics that do appear in the early volumes. 20:26.140 --> 20:32.580 So we're going to mostly focus on the mature Marx. 20:32.578 --> 20:37.278 We're mostly going to focus on Marx as he set himself the task 20:37.279 --> 20:42.059 of understanding the dynamics of capitalism after he had pretty 20:42.057 --> 20:46.137 much given up on his youthful enthusiasm for the quick 20:46.142 --> 20:50.772 transformation of the world into socialist and then communist 20:50.765 --> 20:55.225 societies, which he had basically started 20:55.227 --> 21:01.017 to shed after 1848 with a brief revival of interest in 1870 21:01.021 --> 21:05.971 given events in France, but basically it was a 21:05.971 --> 21:11.911 trajectory from youthful optimism into mature pessimism, 21:11.910 --> 21:16.830 at least from his point of view. 21:16.828 --> 21:21.088 Okay, so what he did was, he said to himself, 21:21.088 --> 21:24.668 "Well, what is it that people are involved in-- 21:24.670 --> 21:28.590 who are engaged in the serious systematic analysis of 21:28.587 --> 21:30.017 capitalism?" 21:30.019 --> 21:35.769 And here we tend to present Marx as an unorthodox or radical 21:35.772 --> 21:41.432 thinker, but in fact he was a very conventional thinker for 21:41.429 --> 21:42.599 his day. 21:42.598 --> 21:48.098 That is to say Marx was a follower of Adam Smith and David 21:48.097 --> 21:52.807 Ricardo, and he saw himself largely as 21:52.809 --> 21:59.859 tackling and refining the theories that they developed. 21:59.858 --> 22:04.258 And what I want to do with the rest of our time this morning is 22:04.255 --> 22:08.575 say something about the project of classical political economy 22:08.579 --> 22:11.699 that Marx inherited and contributed to, 22:11.700 --> 22:15.910 and why he thought getting the basic problems that the 22:15.913 --> 22:20.453 classical political economists were trying to solve solved 22:20.446 --> 22:25.056 would enable us to understand what the real conditions were 22:25.058 --> 22:30.068 that would eventually lead to the collapse of capitalism. 22:30.068 --> 22:36.108 The most important feature of capitalism, 22:36.108 --> 22:40.428 as far as Adam Smith was concerned in The Wealth of 22:40.432 --> 22:43.942 Nations and his followers after him, 22:43.940 --> 22:49.440 was the division of labor. 22:49.440 --> 22:56.470 The division of labor is really important because it has two 22:56.469 --> 22:57.779 features. 22:57.779 --> 23:02.629 One, as far as Marx will be concerned, it begins the process 23:02.633 --> 23:05.433 of alienating us from ourselves. 23:05.430 --> 23:07.210 Why does it do that? 23:07.210 --> 23:12.190 It does that because, instead of producing things 23:12.190 --> 23:18.000 that we then consume, we start producing things in a 23:18.000 --> 23:23.650 situation where we divide up tasks and that makes it 23:23.647 --> 23:28.407 impossible for us to live rounded lives. 23:28.410 --> 23:30.270 That's ultimately where it's going to go. 23:30.269 --> 23:34.139 But second, and much more important from the point of view 23:34.144 --> 23:37.004 of economics, is that the division of labor 23:36.999 --> 23:39.309 is the engine of productivity. 23:39.308 --> 23:43.638 The more you engage in the division of labor the more 23:43.643 --> 23:46.063 productive you make people. 23:46.058 --> 23:50.318 And Smith has this wonderful example right near the beginning 23:50.319 --> 23:54.369 of The Wealth of Nations where he talks about a pin 23:54.366 --> 23:55.216 factory. 23:55.220 --> 23:58.990 Smith has been going around England trying to understand 23:58.991 --> 24:02.011 where the dynamism in the English economy is, 24:02.010 --> 24:05.510 and he gives this description of a pin factory. 24:05.509 --> 24:07.989 He says, One man draws out the wire, 24:07.990 --> 24:10.390 another straights it, a third cuts it, 24:10.387 --> 24:13.427 a fourth points it, a fifth grinds it at the top 24:13.434 --> 24:15.254 for receiving the head. 24:15.250 --> 24:18.890 To make the head requires two or three distinct operations. 24:18.890 --> 24:23.820 To put it on is a peculiar business. 24:23.819 --> 24:25.869 To whiten the pins is another. 24:25.868 --> 24:29.568 It is even a trade by itself to put them into the paper. 24:29.568 --> 24:32.628 And the important business of making a pin is, 24:32.630 --> 24:35.490 in this manner, divided into about eighteen 24:35.487 --> 24:37.117 distinct operations. 24:37.118 --> 24:39.988 As a result of that division of labor, 24:39.990 --> 24:45.780 though, Smith calculated that ten workers could make 48,000 24:45.780 --> 24:48.910 pins a day, but if they had all worked 24:48.912 --> 24:53.042 separately and independently all they could have produced was a 24:53.042 --> 24:53.912 few dozen. 24:53.910 --> 24:57.890 So that basic insight of Smith's, that it's the division 24:57.885 --> 25:02.075 of labor that is the engine of capitalist productivity, 25:02.078 --> 25:06.528 sets the terms for Adam Smith's analysis of markets in The 25:06.528 --> 25:10.308 Wealth of Nations, for Ricardo's 25:10.313 --> 25:15.373 refinement, and for Marx's refinement of both of their 25:15.369 --> 25:18.709 arguments in Das Kapital. 25:18.710 --> 25:27.060 So what was the project of classical political economy? 25:27.058 --> 25:31.588 What was it that Marx was stepping into and trying to 25:31.594 --> 25:32.994 contribute to? 25:32.990 --> 25:39.050 Well, one way of describing it, as I have it here, 25:39.048 --> 25:44.238 is, it was the search for theories of natural and market-- 25:44.240 --> 25:46.750 I've got theories there twice, sorry-- 25:46.750 --> 25:50.220 search for theories of natural and market wages, 25:50.220 --> 25:52.790 prices, rents, and profits. 25:52.788 --> 25:56.088 They wanted to understand what determines wages, 25:56.088 --> 25:57.938 prices, rents, and profits, 25:57.944 --> 26:02.374 but they thought you had to have a theory of natural wages, 26:02.368 --> 26:04.318 prices, rents, and profits, 26:04.318 --> 26:10.458 and market wages, prices, rents, and profits. 26:10.460 --> 26:15.590 Now, let's focus on prices, because the way the other three 26:15.589 --> 26:20.279 are treated is basically by analogy to the analysis of 26:20.278 --> 26:21.338 pricing. 26:21.338 --> 26:26.368 A modern neoclassical economist would say, "There is no 26:26.369 --> 26:29.269 natural price of anything." 26:29.269 --> 26:36.249 A modern neoclassical economist would say, "What determines 26:36.251 --> 26:41.131 prices is supply and demand in the market. 26:41.130 --> 26:45.900 There is nothing else to say about prices." 26:45.900 --> 26:50.980 And they gave up the notion that there's any natural theory 26:50.980 --> 26:55.450 of wages, prices, rents, and profits to be found. 26:55.450 --> 26:58.690 So a big difference between the classical theorists, 26:58.694 --> 27:02.004 and the modern theorists, is this idea that there's a 27:02.003 --> 27:03.853 theory of natural prices. 27:03.848 --> 27:08.138 Now, why would they think there's a theory of natural 27:08.136 --> 27:08.876 prices? 27:08.880 --> 27:13.130 The reason they thought there was a theory of natural prices 27:13.134 --> 27:17.254 was they were arguing with people like the physiocrats and 27:17.247 --> 27:21.067 the trade theorists about where value comes from. 27:21.069 --> 27:23.299 What is the source of value? 27:23.298 --> 27:28.958 The physiocrats in France said the source of value is the land, 27:28.955 --> 27:33.605 that somehow it gets transferred to the products. 27:33.608 --> 27:37.458 Whereas the trade theorists, who had been impressed that 27:37.460 --> 27:41.940 countries like Holland which had so little land but had become so 27:41.940 --> 27:43.660 rich said, "No. 27:43.659 --> 27:45.889 Value comes from trade." 27:45.890 --> 27:50.160 So they were all sort of saying, "Where is the it? 27:50.160 --> 27:53.420 What is the source of value?" 27:53.420 --> 27:57.320 And the English theorists following Locke, 27:57.323 --> 28:01.513 Petty--Sir William Petty, John Locke, Hobbes, 28:01.510 --> 28:07.700 all believed that the way you find value is to go into labor; 28:07.700 --> 28:12.600 that work, workmanship is the source of value. 28:12.598 --> 28:15.398 So all classical political economists, 28:15.400 --> 28:20.640 Smith, Ricardo and Marx believed in the labor theory of 28:20.636 --> 28:23.236 value, and they counter posed it to 28:23.236 --> 28:26.936 theories based on trade, or the physiocrats' theories 28:26.940 --> 28:32.500 that were popular in France, as I've said. 28:32.500 --> 28:36.370 So that's one reason, but another is that it's not 28:36.373 --> 28:40.883 the case that they were ignorant of the laws of supply and 28:40.880 --> 28:41.750 demand. 28:41.750 --> 28:47.960 So and we'll see how Marx handles them on Wednesday. 28:47.960 --> 28:52.260 It's not the case that they're ignorant of the laws of supply 28:52.256 --> 28:56.616 and demand, but they thought it couldn't possibly tell you the 28:56.624 --> 28:57.774 whole story. 28:57.769 --> 28:59.749 So you can think about it this way. 28:59.750 --> 29:07.920 Suppose there is a dearth in the supply of coffee mugs? 29:07.920 --> 29:10.770 The price will go up. 29:10.769 --> 29:14.579 They didn't disagree with that, right? 29:14.578 --> 29:17.908 And if there are too many coffee mugs, more coffee mugs 29:17.906 --> 29:20.676 than anybody wants, the price will go down. 29:20.680 --> 29:25.040 Maybe somebody will realize you an drill holes in the bottom and 29:25.038 --> 29:29.418 then use them to grow plants in, and then maybe the price would 29:29.417 --> 29:32.027 go up a bit because there will be more. 29:32.028 --> 29:35.938 But they thought that supply and demand fluctuate with what 29:35.938 --> 29:38.228 it is that people actually want. 29:38.230 --> 29:41.070 They didn't have any problem with that notion, 29:41.068 --> 29:45.258 but still in all they thought there must be something that 29:45.260 --> 29:49.670 will tell you what the price is when supply and demand are in 29:49.673 --> 29:50.853 equilibrium. 29:50.848 --> 29:54.958 Another way you can think about it is supply and demand go up 29:54.958 --> 29:57.878 and down, but they go up and down around 29:57.880 --> 30:03.020 some point, and what tells you what that 30:03.019 --> 30:04.529 point is? 30:04.528 --> 30:08.078 Okay, that's what the labor theory of value was supposed to 30:08.083 --> 30:08.393 do. 30:08.390 --> 30:10.550 That's the natural price. 30:10.548 --> 30:15.298 I think a modern economist might call it the long-run 30:15.301 --> 30:17.131 equilibrium price. 30:17.130 --> 30:21.470 That's one way in which if you wanted to find an analogy in 30:21.470 --> 30:25.890 modern economic thinking to this classical idea of a natural 30:25.885 --> 30:28.635 price, it's the long-run equilibrium 30:28.643 --> 30:29.113 price. 30:29.108 --> 30:33.978 It's the price of a commodity when supply and demand are in 30:33.982 --> 30:35.162 equilibrium. 30:35.160 --> 30:43.400 So the labor theory of value was a theory of that. 30:43.400 --> 30:46.980 It was going to tell you what the long-run equilibrium price 30:46.984 --> 30:48.934 of a commodity would be, okay? 30:48.930 --> 30:52.810 And all of the classical political economists were trying 30:52.808 --> 30:54.678 to have a theory of that. 30:54.680 --> 30:57.460 So when you read "natural prices," 30:57.457 --> 30:59.457 that's what you should think. 30:59.460 --> 31:02.690 They're trying to understand what-- 31:02.690 --> 31:06.980 not marginal changes in the sense of a Pareto diagram, 31:06.980 --> 31:12.400 but the long-run changes given the marginal fluctuations around 31:12.402 --> 31:13.542 some point. 31:13.538 --> 31:15.638 The question is, what is that point? 31:15.640 --> 31:19.990 And that's what the labor theory of value was designed to 31:19.986 --> 31:20.836 give you. 31:20.838 --> 31:22.868 It was a theory, in that sense, 31:22.865 --> 31:26.305 of natural prices, not a theory of market prices. 31:26.308 --> 31:28.098 They thought you had to have both. 31:28.098 --> 31:30.348 Supply and demand gave you the market price. 31:30.348 --> 31:35.408 The labor theory of value gave you the natural price. 31:35.410 --> 31:40.760 A second big problem that framed the project of classical 31:40.756 --> 31:45.336 political economy was that they all believed, 31:45.338 --> 31:50.048 as they looked around them, that there was a declining 31:50.048 --> 31:52.978 tendency in the rate of profit. 31:52.980 --> 32:02.230 This was taken as a given; as a given, widely-accepted 32:02.228 --> 32:04.388 empirical fact. 32:04.390 --> 32:10.600 And so if it was the case that the rate of profit tends to 32:10.601 --> 32:14.381 decline over time, it can be offset by various 32:14.380 --> 32:16.810 things and so on which we will talk about, 32:16.808 --> 32:20.658 but if it's the case that the rate of profit in capitalist 32:20.659 --> 32:25.209 economies declines over time, your theory isn't going to be 32:25.205 --> 32:28.575 worth a damn unless you can explain why. 32:28.578 --> 32:31.148 So one of the tests, if you like, 32:31.152 --> 32:35.092 of a good theory, as far as Smith was concerned, 32:35.085 --> 32:37.715 as far as Ricardo was concerned, 32:37.720 --> 32:41.960 and as far as Marx was concerned, was it had to explain 32:41.964 --> 32:45.664 the declining tendency in the rate of profit. 32:45.660 --> 32:49.340 And Smith had an account, Ricardo had an account, 32:49.344 --> 32:51.344 and Marx had an account. 32:51.339 --> 32:52.379 They all differed somewhat. 32:52.380 --> 32:55.120 They all overlapped in some ways. 32:55.118 --> 32:59.288 We'll see part of the reason all three of them thought you 32:59.291 --> 33:03.611 would have to have imperialism was you needed new markets to 33:03.609 --> 33:07.709 offset this problem of the declining tendency in the rate 33:07.710 --> 33:12.050 of profit at home, but that was only going to be a 33:12.045 --> 33:14.545 temporary stopgap or solution. 33:14.548 --> 33:18.158 But in any event, your theory wasn't going to be 33:18.162 --> 33:22.932 worth anything unless it could explain why prices are what they 33:22.928 --> 33:24.998 are, the theory of long-run 33:25.000 --> 33:30.910 equilibrium prices, and second, unless it gave a 33:30.907 --> 33:41.067 credible account of why profits fall in capitalist systems over 33:41.067 --> 33:42.377 time. 33:42.380 --> 33:47.570 Now, a third conceptual point to make that you need in order 33:47.567 --> 33:52.667 to understand the project of classical political economy as 33:52.669 --> 33:58.209 Marx understood it is actually related to the first point, 33:58.210 --> 34:02.000 but I'm just singling it out because people sometimes get 34:01.997 --> 34:03.347 confused about it. 34:03.348 --> 34:07.938 It's a distinction that Marx makes between use-value and 34:07.940 --> 34:09.360 exchange value. 34:09.360 --> 34:15.800 Sometimes you'll see Marx uses the word value with a big V. 34:15.800 --> 34:19.300 You should just read that as exchange value. 34:19.300 --> 34:27.810 So value with a big V is exchange value. 34:27.809 --> 34:31.339 So what is the difference between use-value and exchange 34:31.344 --> 34:31.864 value? 34:31.860 --> 34:36.620 Well, for Marx use-value is utility. 34:36.619 --> 34:40.779 That's all it is. 34:40.780 --> 34:45.340 Use-value is simply usefulness. 34:45.340 --> 34:49.790 And he has a kind of binary theory of use-value. 34:49.789 --> 34:52.809 Either things have use value or they don't. 34:52.809 --> 34:55.729 So coffee cups have a use-value, you can drink out of 34:55.726 --> 34:56.116 them. 34:56.119 --> 34:59.169 If somebody drilled holes in the bottom of them they would 34:59.166 --> 35:02.156 have no use-value until somebody came along and said, 35:02.159 --> 35:04.479 "Well, we can use them to grow plants," 35:04.476 --> 35:06.066 then they would have use-value. 35:06.070 --> 35:09.110 So things either have use-value or they don't, 35:09.114 --> 35:11.894 and I'll come back to that in a minute. 35:11.889 --> 35:15.869 And that's going to affect the supply and demand, 35:15.867 --> 35:19.347 but it's not going to explain the price. 35:19.349 --> 35:24.109 It's not going to explain the long-run equilibrium price. 35:24.110 --> 35:28.770 That is the exchange value and that is what we learn about from 35:28.766 --> 35:33.046 the labor theory of value as far as Marx was concerned. 35:33.050 --> 35:38.070 So it's the labor theory of value explains the price, 35:38.068 --> 35:43.858 and is not to be confused with the use-value or utility of an 35:43.858 --> 35:44.918 object. 35:44.920 --> 35:48.500 Again, one important difference, and maybe the most 35:48.501 --> 35:52.731 important difference between classical political economy and 35:52.726 --> 35:55.516 neoclassical political economy is, 35:55.518 --> 35:58.848 we will see later, the neoclassical people shed 35:58.851 --> 36:03.051 the labor theory of value and so there is no exchange value 36:03.052 --> 36:06.562 independent of utility, but we'll get to that. 36:06.559 --> 36:08.379 That's getting ahead of ourselves. 36:08.380 --> 36:13.110 When you're concerned with the classical formulations, 36:13.110 --> 36:17.320 and in the nineteenth century, exchange value or price, 36:17.320 --> 36:22.510 or value with a big V, is determined by the labor 36:22.512 --> 36:27.492 theory of value and use-value is usefulness. 36:27.489 --> 36:35.069 And that brings me to Marx's definition of a commodity. 36:35.070 --> 36:39.860 36:39.860 --> 36:45.300 A commodity has a very special meaning for Marx. 36:45.300 --> 36:51.520 It's something that is produced for exchange. 36:51.518 --> 36:58.388 So if you plant an apple tree and you grow apples in order to 36:58.387 --> 37:05.137 eat them, you're producing for consumption, those apples are 37:05.139 --> 37:07.429 not commodities. 37:07.429 --> 37:12.169 But if you plant an apple tree and grow apples and sell them, 37:12.170 --> 37:15.570 then those apples are commodities, right? 37:15.570 --> 37:21.320 And something is a commodity if it's produced for exchange. 37:21.320 --> 37:24.690 And that's very important because once you have a division 37:24.693 --> 37:27.953 of labor you have more and more commodity production. 37:27.949 --> 37:33.239 And you might recall in my very first lecture I said that one of 37:33.242 --> 37:38.362 the things Marx shares in common with Bentham is he's somebody 37:38.364 --> 37:43.244 who pushes the idea he has to the absolute extreme and then 37:43.237 --> 37:45.167 even beyond that. 37:45.170 --> 37:49.940 So what we're going to see happen with Marx and 37:49.936 --> 37:55.116 commodification is exactly analogous to Bentham and 37:55.115 --> 37:56.355 utility. 37:56.360 --> 37:59.990 That Bentham says, "How would the world look 37:59.985 --> 38:03.985 if utility maximization was the only game in town, 38:03.989 --> 38:07.589 if there was nothing else at all?" 38:07.590 --> 38:09.410 and so his theory runs. 38:09.409 --> 38:12.709 With Marx it's, "How would the world look 38:12.710 --> 38:16.600 if commodification was the only game in town?" 38:16.599 --> 38:22.589 Everything in a capitalist system becomes a commodity, 38:22.590 --> 38:25.530 even the worker himself. 38:25.530 --> 38:27.230 Even the worker himself. 38:27.230 --> 38:31.660 And when we start to understand the dynamics of capitalist 38:31.661 --> 38:35.941 production we'll see that the analysis of the value of a 38:35.936 --> 38:40.826 worker is no different than the analysis of the value of the pin 38:40.833 --> 38:45.113 that the worker produces in Adam Smith's factory. 38:45.110 --> 38:50.950 So he takes this idea of commodification and pushes it to 38:50.952 --> 38:52.102 the hilt. 38:52.099 --> 38:57.649 So I think if you think about those four features of the 38:57.648 --> 39:03.798 project of classical political economy it gives you a sense of 39:03.802 --> 39:09.652 what was in Marx's head as he set off to try and understand 39:09.652 --> 39:13.792 the dynamics of capitalist systems. 39:13.789 --> 39:18.849 And what he did was, he said, "Well, 39:18.849 --> 39:23.219 we have to understand, first of all, 39:23.219 --> 39:30.089 how capitalist systems look to the participants, 39:30.090 --> 39:34.990 because the way in which they look to the participants is not 39:34.994 --> 39:39.414 the same as the way in which they really work." 39:39.409 --> 39:41.979 So there's a basic distinction, if you like, 39:41.978 --> 39:43.948 between appearance and reality. 39:43.949 --> 39:49.159 The way in which people think market systems work isn't the 39:49.163 --> 39:52.223 way in which they actually work. 39:52.219 --> 39:54.119 So it's a little like Bentham saying, 39:54.119 --> 39:58.819 "You might think you're not motivated by utility and all 39:58.820 --> 40:01.330 the rest of it, but in fact you are, 40:01.327 --> 40:03.467 and the rare case is we get it right, 40:03.469 --> 40:05.859 not the rare case is that we get it wrong." 40:05.860 --> 40:07.960 In this sense Marx, like Bentham, 40:07.958 --> 40:09.268 is an objectivist. 40:09.268 --> 40:13.148 He thinks he's describing scientifically the laws of 40:13.146 --> 40:17.176 motion of capitalist systems regardless of whether the 40:17.175 --> 40:22.265 participants in those systems understand these laws of motion, 40:22.268 --> 40:26.038 and for the most part they don't. 40:26.039 --> 40:29.799 Indeed he's going to claim ultimately that a socialist 40:29.795 --> 40:33.685 revolution differs from all others because for the first 40:33.692 --> 40:37.272 time in history, people understand the social 40:37.268 --> 40:42.768 relations that they're part of, and so can self-consciously 40:42.768 --> 40:48.958 transform them and create an unalienated social order. 40:48.960 --> 40:53.470 So at the beginning of volume one of Kapital he's 40:53.465 --> 40:57.235 basically saying, "How does it look to the 40:57.235 --> 40:59.115 participants?" 40:59.119 --> 41:03.449 Well, if you have a division of labor, you look around, 41:03.452 --> 41:05.622 what do you actually see? 41:05.619 --> 41:10.419 You see people producing commodities. 41:10.420 --> 41:15.380 They exchange those commodities for money, and then they use 41:15.382 --> 41:20.262 that money to buy other commodities, which they consume. 41:20.260 --> 41:23.340 So you have these cycles of exchange; 41:23.340 --> 41:27.680 commodity, money, commodity, right? 41:27.679 --> 41:32.769 So the person working growing apples, sells the apples for 41:32.768 --> 41:38.208 money, and then uses the money to buy milk and eggs and so on, 41:38.213 --> 41:41.073 in the simplest case, right? 41:41.070 --> 41:45.790 So if someone landed from Mars in the middle of a capitalist 41:45.789 --> 41:48.829 economy, that's what they would see; 41:48.829 --> 41:52.529 all of these people producing things, exchanging those things 41:52.532 --> 41:56.112 for money, and buying other things which they then consume, 41:56.112 --> 41:56.732 right? 41:56.730 --> 41:59.740 That was the idea. 41:59.739 --> 42:03.839 But then if you look a little bit more carefully, 42:03.840 --> 42:08.280 you see that actually some people are doing something 42:08.284 --> 42:10.254 entirely different. 42:10.250 --> 42:13.400 Most people are producing commodities, exchanging the 42:13.402 --> 42:16.922 commodities for money and then using the money to buy other 42:16.918 --> 42:18.978 commodities that they consume. 42:18.980 --> 42:22.560 But Marx says, "Some people are doing 42:22.559 --> 42:24.479 something different. 42:24.480 --> 42:30.010 They're taking some money, buying a commodity (in this 42:30.007 --> 42:36.677 case the labor of the worker for a certain time) and then selling 42:36.681 --> 42:41.271 what gets produced for more money." 42:41.268 --> 42:45.708 So they're not interested in consumption it doesn't seem, 42:45.708 --> 42:47.768 at least at first sight. 42:47.768 --> 42:54.608 And indeed, if you look even more closely you'll see that 42:54.605 --> 43:00.335 when they do that, the money they end up with is 43:00.342 --> 43:05.472 more than the money they started with. 43:05.469 --> 43:10.209 M prime is bigger than M. 43:10.210 --> 43:13.400 And the question, the organizing question of 43:13.398 --> 43:17.208 Das Kapital-- and it was the question that 43:17.211 --> 43:21.501 preoccupied Adam Smith and David Ricardo before Marx, 43:21.500 --> 43:24.110 and as I said, in this sense he was completely 43:24.110 --> 43:29.580 orthodox classical theorist, his radicalism comes in later. 43:29.579 --> 43:32.659 The question is where does prime come from? 43:32.659 --> 43:36.859 What makes profit possible? 43:36.860 --> 43:39.910 You're not going to explain why profits decline, 43:39.914 --> 43:43.304 after all, if you can't understand where profit comes 43:43.295 --> 43:43.875 from. 43:43.880 --> 43:53.040 What is the origin of profit? 43:53.039 --> 43:57.069 That's the basic problem. 43:57.070 --> 44:00.950 The transformation of money into capital has to be developed 44:00.952 --> 44:04.312 on the basis of the immanent laws of the exchange of 44:04.309 --> 44:07.799 commodities, in such a way that the starting 44:07.797 --> 44:10.697 point is the exchange of equivalents. 44:10.699 --> 44:14.909 The money-owner who is as yet only the capitalist in larval 44:14.909 --> 44:17.459 form, must buy his commodities at 44:17.458 --> 44:20.408 their value, sell them at their value, 44:20.409 --> 44:24.809 and yet at the end of the process withdraw more value from 44:24.809 --> 44:28.979 circulation than he threw into it at the beginning. 44:28.980 --> 44:33.660 His emergence as a butterfly must, and yet must not, 44:33.663 --> 44:37.523 take place in the sphere of circulation. 44:37.518 --> 44:40.888 These are the conditions of the problem. 44:40.889 --> 44:45.829 A very famous passage at the beginning of Kapital 44:45.829 --> 44:51.129 telling us that if you want to understand why the capitalist 44:51.130 --> 44:57.150 winds up with more you have to understand the source of value, 44:57.150 --> 45:02.850 because there's no cheating; equivalents exchange for 45:02.853 --> 45:06.083 equivalents in every one of those cycles. 45:06.079 --> 45:09.519 It's not that somehow the worker is tricked into selling 45:09.521 --> 45:12.151 his labor power for less than its worth. 45:12.150 --> 45:15.480 On the contrary, he's paid exactly what its 45:15.476 --> 45:16.106 worth. 45:16.110 --> 45:21.630 So once you can understand that puzzle of how, 45:21.630 --> 45:24.540 when equivalents exchange for equivalents, 45:24.539 --> 45:28.559 new value is still nonetheless created, 45:28.559 --> 45:32.069 then you understand the secret to where profit comes from, 45:32.070 --> 45:36.550 you know the source of value, and you can begin the process 45:36.550 --> 45:41.190 of understanding the dynamic productiveness of capitalism and 45:41.188 --> 45:44.818 why it will eventually start to fall apart. 45:44.820 --> 45:48.800 And we will dig into those subjects on Wednesday. 45:48.800 --> 45:54.000